A Life Worth Living by Robert Zaretsky


Zaretsky, R. (2013). A Life Worth Living [Kindle Android version]. Retrieved from Amazon.com


Prologue

Page 7

It is this persistent uneasiness, this unhappy inability to be lulled by the rationalizations we give for our own actions or the actions of others, this accursed gift of forcing not just oneself, but those around one, to reconsider beliefs one has always taken for granted, that makes Camus so important.

Page 8

exigency. He was a moralist who insisted that while the world is absurd and allows for no hope, we are not condemned to despair; a moralist who reminded us that, in the end, all we have is one another in an indifferent and silent world:

Page 9

The best the agent can do is to have his suffering, the natural expression of his goodness of character, and not to stifle these responses out of misguided optimism.”

1. Absurdity

Page 12

the absurd “poisons our everydayness and gives our every experience a tinge of futility.… We find ourselves desperately trying to move more quickly, to nowhere; or we try to ‘entertain ourselves.’

Page 13

This view forces upon us truths that are both prosaic and paralyzing— that we need never have lived or that the world will continue without the faintest of shudders when we die. In seeing ourselves from the outside, Nagel notes, “we find it difficult to take our lives seriously.” At such moments, we confront absurdity— a “genuine problem which we cannot ignore.”

Page 13

For Camus, however, this astonishment results from our confrontation with a world that refuses to surrender meaning. It occurs when our need for meaning shatters against the indifference, immovable and absolute, of the world. As a result, absurdity is not an autonomous state; it does not exist in the world, but is instead exhaled from the abyss that divides us from a mute world. “This

Page 16

Sartre described a world awash in pure contingency. Caught in the undertow of events for which there is no ultimate or external justification, Sartre observed, we are overcome with a sense of nausea.

Page 24

Camus creates a character whose life is empty of the shade offered by self- reflection.

Page 25

changed.” 28 With life yoked so tightly to the present that no space remains for what precedes or follows, nothing changes.

Page 25

Or, more accurately, it is with reflection that we see change. Moreover, it is only with change that we see reflection— our own.

Page 25

This is the paradox Meursault makes flesh: for him, only life lived in the moment— the moment our bodies register sensations sweeping over them— is meaningful.

Page 25

Rousseau affirmed that man in his natural state was the happiest of beings because he was, quite simply, the dumbest of beings.

Page 26

Absurdity enters our life only when the prison door clangs shut— or when, from the heights of society we measure how far we have fallen.

Page 28

Absurdity is the child of disparity. It rises before us when our expectations fall short of reality.

Page 29

As for the exodus, what greater disparity could there be for the millions of refugees who, just days before they were pulled into the vortex created by the capsizing of the French Republic, still believed stupidly in the permanence of their civil, legal, and political institutions, as well as the durability of their everyday lives?

Page 30

It is the moment when we are woken from our routine lives by a whisper or explosion, either of which demands “Why?” with equal and unexpected insistence.

Page 36

Boredom was even more terrible if you did not have a job.

Page 38

Camus. It is as if the torment inflicted by the gods has little if anything to do with a body taxed beyond measure, and everything to do with a mind challenged by the endlessly repetitive nature of the task.

Page 38

The weight of the labor is not the consequence of gravity, but instead found in the gravity of its inconsequential nature.

Page 39

Sispyhus is bound to the boulder, of course, but, more important, he is bound to the absurdity of his relationship with the boulder.

Page 44

“You cannot hear him, but you see his incomprehensible dumb show: you wonder why he is alive.”

Page 45

This particular aesthetic, in turn, reveals a truth about the human condition that formal arguments simply cannot: we live in a world that refuses to signify, and thus risks transforming our acts and words into spasms of arbitrary and senseless gestures.

Page 48

He allows that these failed arguments persist because they reflect something true and enduring about our lives: the shock we feel when, stepping outside ourselves and adopting “the view from nowhere,” we suddenly confront the dissonance between the great importance we devote to our daily activities and their ultimate inconsequentiality.

Page 49

At this point, Nagel declares, “we see ourselves from outside, and all the contingency and specificity of our aims and pursuits become clear. Yet when we take this view and recognize what we do as arbitrary, it does not disengage us from life, and there lies our absurdity.”

Page 50

Ironic detachment is tantamount to the wearing of philosophical blinders. But to a man who puts them aside, Camus writes, “there is no finer sight than that of the intelligence at grips with a reality that transcends it.… To impoverish that reality whose inhumanity constitutes man’s majesty is tantamount to impoverishing him himself. I understand then why the doctrines that explain everything to me also debilitate me at the same time. They relieve me of the weight of my own life.”

Page 52

Resistance is, first and foremost, a way of seeing the world, one that makes manifest the moral imperative to acknowledge and respect the dignity of each and every fellow human being.

Page 55

Finally roused, God speaks through a whirlwind, demanding who it is that “darkeneth counsel by words without knowledge? Gird up now thy loins like a man; for I will demand of thee, and answer thou me. Where wast thou when I laid the foundations of the earth? Declare, if thou hast understanding.” The storm- tossed voice launches dozens of similar questions, all of them equally irrelevant to Job’s quest for meaning. By the end of this battering, Job confesses that he had no right to demand to know the reasons why he suffered. The sheer incommensurability between God’s perspective and Job’s, it seems, is reason enough.

Page 58

The absurd, Camus wrote in 1942, “teaches nothing.” 96 Instead of looking at ourselves, as do Sisyphus, Meursault, or even Job, we must look to others: we are, Camus recognized, condemned to live together in this silent world.

Page 58

“The misery and greatness of this world: it offers no truths, but only objects for love. Absurdity is king, but love saves us from it.”

2. Silence

Page 64

Even more than the sea, the figure of the silent mother occupies the center of Camus’ writings: it is the sun, or perhaps the dark matter, toward which everything else is pulled.

Page 65

Rather than the consequence of human expectations, the absence we encounter when our ears strain, but fail to hear something, it is instead a positive force, one far older than humankind, perhaps older than the world itself.

Page 66

Like a solar eclipse, two orbs of silence overlap: the blinding and incommunicable reality of Prometheus’s pain and the shadow cast by an indifferent and mute world.

Page 67

These silences surge, in part, from Prometheus’s failure to find words adequate to the tasks at hand; they spell the breakdown of language.

Page 68

Given over entirely to himself, Camus felt defenseless against these “deep forces rising within me that said ‘no.’ ” No, in a word, to plans for the future, to talk about tomorrow, to things not yet done. Instead, Camus demands the weight of the present, of the earth, of a world shorn of its myths and faith in anything other than what we can see and touch and feel.

Page 68

This destiny is reflected in the fates of Prometheus and Sisyphus: to accept what they have done, embrace what they have been given, and survey silently a silent universe.

Page 70

Camus encountered the staggering distance between word and facts.

Page 70

His earlier perception of silence as a condition crucial to self- understanding is overtaken by the recollection that silence also serves political and ideological ends.

Page 71

Marveling at the abyss between the ideals of the Republic and reality of Kabylia, Camus refused to surrender his ideals.

Page 76

Framed by endless horizons, filled with blinding light and preternatural calm, Camus claimed this world of “silence and solitude” as a source of truth.

Page 77

The demand for wooden barrels was shrinking and, in order to maintain his profit margin, Lassalle cannot afford to raise salaries. And what would happen if the entire atelier went under? “A man doesn’t change trades when he’s taken the trouble to learn one, and a difficult one, demanding a long apprenticeship.” Giving up his trade was unthinkable, but so too was resigning himself to an inadequate paycheck and knowing his labor was undervalued. In so unforgiving a situation, “it was difficult to close your mouth.”

Page 77

Yet, by the time he reaches the workshop, this is precisely what Yvars and his fellow workers will do.

Page 78

Unwittingly, Yvars has repeated the same sentiment offered just moments earlier by Lassalle— with the difference that, this time, the extended hand is accepted.

Page 80

occupied France and the Algiers workshop, a silence born in humiliation slowly becomes a silence braced by the nearly instinctive insistence on dignity.

Page 81

Today we tend to regard silence as the interruption of noise, but once we recover from the effects of sound, we realize that silence’s primordial function is to provide a kind of basso continuo to the drama of our lives.

Page 82

In the end, the trouble may be the simple and tragic impossibility of speaking across lives and the predicaments specific to each and every one of them.

Page 86

Words had proved at best useless, at worst complicit in the widening gyre of violence in Algeria. Just as with his mother, when he felt, silently, an “immense pity spread out around him,” so too with the student: “When one keeps quiet, the situation becomes clear.” 51 The tragic situation of his native Algeria, Camus realized, called upon him to maintain his quiet.

Page 86

the equally sublime wonder of the world and ethical duties of the individual.

Page 88

“He diagnosed in himself, and in others, the inability to believe and the disappearance of the primitive foundation of all faith— namely, the belief in life.”

Page 91

Like his mother, like us, perhaps even like Socrates, Camus suffered life he never believed we needed to overcome.

3. Measure

Page 96

In a manifesto penned by Camus, the company declared its intent “to demonstrate that it is sometimes advantageous to art to descend from its ivory tower… [and] restore some human values.”

Page 97

“The spirit of revolution lies wholly in man’s protest against the human condition. Under the different forms that it assumes, it is… the only eternal theme of art and religion. A revolution is always carried out against the Gods— from that of Prometheus onwards.”

Page 98

11 Yet more emphatically, Tipasa, this gateway to antiquity, makes him understand “what is meant by glory: the right to love without limits.”

Page 102

In his reply, Camus now straddles the political and metaphysical, physical and spiritual worlds: “Prometheus was the hero who loved men enough to give them fire and liberty, technology and art. Today, mankind needs and cares only for technology. We rebel through our machines, holding art and what art implies as an obstacle and a symbol of slavery. But what characterizes Prometheus is that he cannot separate machines from art.”

Page 102

Had this same Prometheus, so hated by Zeus, appeared amid the rubble of postwar Europe, the era’s great technological and ideological actors would also have hauled him away: “They would nail him to a rock, in the name of the very humanism he was the first to symbolize.”

Page 104

Indiscriminate and ineluctable, force levels the strong and weak, transforming victim and victimizer into “things.”

Page 104

Yet those in power consistently abuse their authority, unaware that their mastery of force is utterly illusory.

Page 105

It is a universe where both Prometheus and Zeus are right, but neither is justified, a universe where the gods impose the impossible choice on Agamemnon of either sacrificing his daughter or abandoning his effort to retrieve Helen and Greek honor.

Page 106

The people who suffered from these policies “are not inferior except in regard to the conditions in which they must live,”

Page 106

France’s duty was clear: it had to “quell the cruelest of hungers and heal inflamed hearts.”

Page 106

Camus insisted upon the universal quality of human dignity, all the while holding on to the particularity of individual human beings.

Bookmark -Page 107

Page 108

Prometheus is both just and unjust, and Zeus who pitilessly oppresses him also has right on his side. Melodrama could thus be summed up by saying: “Only one side is just and justifiable,” while the perfect tragic formula would be: “All can be justified, no one is just.” This is why the chorus in classical tragedies generally advises prudence. For the chorus knows that up to a certain limit everyone is right and that the person who, from blindness or passion, oversteps this limit is heading for catastrophe if he persists in his desire to assert a right he thinks he alone possesses.

Page 108

The central concern of classical tragedy, Camus realized, is that limit “must not be transgressed. On either side of this limit equally legitimate forces meet in quivering and endless confrontation. To make a mistake about this limit, to try to destroy the balance, is to perish.”

Page 110

In a recent work, the political theorist Aurelian Craiutu insists that moderation is a positive theory, one based on the intrinsic values of pluralism, gradualism, and toleration.

Page 110

moderate, Craiutu suggests, is a thinker who embraces “fallibilism as a middle way between radical skepticism and epistemological absolutism, and acknowledge[ s] the limits of political action and the imperfection of the human condition.”

Page 115

As Nussbaum underscores, tragedy teaches: “There is a kind of knowing that works by suffering because suffering is the appropriate acknowledgement of the way human life, in these cases, is.”

Page 116

“Through suffering comes knowledge.”

4. Fidelity

Page 118

Camus’ loyalty to the visceral ethics expressed by his father— the intuitive conviction that humankind, if it wishes to preserve this status, must obey certain limits on its freedom, all the while acknowledging the humanity of one’s fellow men and women— endured his entire life.

Page 119

It was an ethics based on faithfulness to our fundamental duties and faithfulness to our world.

Page 120

the outrage of a meaningless cosmos impels all of humankind to struggle against it.

Page 120

Camus “merely wanted men to rediscover their solidarity in order to wage war against their revolting fate.”

Page 122

Resentment, after all, is fidelity to an unworthy emotion: hatred or anger.

Page 122

As such, it has no place in an ethics that insists the ends can never justify the means— and no less important, the means are at times justified only by their ends.

Page 122

When asked whether faithfulness can justify a life, Camus replied it could and must— if the faithfulness served life and happiness, not death and servitude. “Undoubtedly, one of the last questions a man can ask about the value of his life is ‘Have I been faithful?’ But this question means nothing if it does not first of all mean ‘Have I done nothing to degrade my life or another’s?’

Page 126

Scarcely twenty years after the Nazi occupiers and French collaborators, in their doomed effort to eradicate the Resistance, had tortured and killed hundreds of Frenchmen and women, French were now torturing Algerian men and women for the same reasons.

Page 126

The French army’s justification for the use of torture was straightforward and compelling: France was at war with a terrorist organization whose bombings and assassinations had taken the lives of hundreds of innocent Frenchmen, women, and children.

Page 127

As he wrote to his friend, the Kabyle writer Mouloud Feraoun: “When language is thoughtlessly used to dispose of human lives, being silent is not a negative quality.”

Page 129

Like Camus, he feared those who argued that a good and great end could justify violent and evil means.

Page 129

“If I have always refused to lie… it is because I could never accept solitude. But solitude should now also be accepted.”

Page 130

For now, we must at the very least reject every justification, even that of effectiveness, for such methods. From the very moment we justify them, even indirectly, neither rule nor value can exist, all claims are equally valid and war without limit or laws consecrates the triumph of nihilism.”

Page 131

Among Camus’ average values was the conviction that the end must never justify the means. Once this rule is violated, well- intentioned men and women will begin their race toward incompatible goals, leaving behind them the trampled remainder of humankind.

Page 135

In other words, his memory of the world— the object of his fidelity— was fading while his preoccupation with ideas grew.

Page 135

The moral imagination, for Camus as for Simone Weil, is the work of attention. Attention to the physical world in its inflexible and indifferent attitude toward us, attention to our fellow human beings in our common struggle to resist this cosmic indifference.

Page 135

But Camus’ essays also reflect Weil’s portrayal of the ways in which force, be it war or factories or governments, transforms human beings into things.